Low-Complexity Tilings of the Plane

05/10/2019
by   Jarkko Kari, et al.
0

A two-dimensional configuration is a coloring of the infinite grid Z^2 with finitely many colors. For a finite subset D of Z^2, the D-patterns of a configuration are the colored patterns of shape D that appear in the configuration. The number of distinct D-patterns of a configuration is a natural measure of its complexity. A configuration is considered having low complexity with respect to shape D if the number of distinct D-patterns is at most |D|, the size of the shape. This extended abstract is a short review of an algebraic method to study periodicity of such low complexity configurations.

READ FULL TEXT VIEW PDF

page 1

page 2

page 3

page 4

04/02/2019

Decidability and Periodicity of Low Complexity Tilings

We investigate the tiling problem, also known as the domino problem, tha...
10/15/2017

Nivat's conjecture holds for sums of two periodic configurations

Nivat's conjecture is a long-standing open combinatorial problem. It con...
07/06/2022

Low complexity, low probability patterns and consequences for algorithmic probability applications

Developing new ways to estimate probabilities can be valuable for scienc...
02/20/2020

Cutting Corners

We define and study a class of subshifts of finite type (SFTs) defined b...
09/09/2022

A Variational Approach to Parameter Estimation for Characterizing 2-D Cluster Variation Method Topographies

One of the biggest challenges in characterizing 2-D topographies is succ...
06/19/2019

Existence of a Convex Polyhedron with Respect to the Given Radii

Given a set of radii measured from a fixed point, the existence of a con...
10/08/2019

Computational complexity in algebraic regression

We analyze the complexity of fitting a variety, coming from a class of v...

1 Introduction

Commutative algebra provides powerful tools to analyze low complexity configurations, that is, colorings of the two-dimensional grid that have sufficiently low number of different local patterns. If the colors are represented as numbers, the low complexity assumption implies that the configuration is a linear combination of its translated copies. This condition can be expressed as an annihilation property under the multiplication of a power series representation of the configuration by a non-zero two-variate polynomial, leading to the study of the ideal of all annihilating polynomials. It turns out that the ideal of annihilators is essentially a principal ideal generated by a product of so-called line polynomials, i.e., univariate polynomials of two-variate monomials. This opens up the possibility to obtain results on global structures of the configuration, such as its periodicity. We first proposed this approach in [icalp, icalpfull] to study Nivat’s conjecture. It led to a number of subsequent results [focs, karimoutot, cai, szabados]. In this presentation we review the main results without proofs – the given references can be consulted for more details. We start by briefly recalling the notations and basic concepts.

1.1 Configurations and periodicity

A -dimensional configuration over a finite alphabet is an assignment of symbols of on the infinite grid . For any configuration and any cell , we denote by the symbol that has in cell

. For any vector

, the translation by shifts a configuration so that for all . We say that is periodic if for some non-zero . In this case is a vector of periodicity and is also termed -periodic. We mostly consider the two-dimensional setting

. In this case, if there are two linearly independent vectors of periodicity then

is called two-periodic. A two-periodic has automatically horizontal and vertical vectors of periodicity and for some , and consequently a vector of periodicity in every rational direction. A two-dimensional periodic configuration that is not two-periodic is called one-periodic.

1.2 Pattern complexity

Let be a finite set of cells, a shape. A -pattern is an assignment of symbols in shape . A (finite) pattern is a -pattern for some finite . Let us denote by the set of all finite patterns over alphabet , where the dimension is assumed to be known from the context. We say that a finite pattern of shape appears in configuration if for some we have . We also say that contains pattern . For a fixed , the set of -patterns that appear in a configuration is denoted by . We denote by the set of all finite patterns that appear in , i.e., the union of over all finite .

The pattern complexity of a configuration with respect to a shape is the number of -patterns that contains. A sufficiently low pattern complexity forces global regularities in a configuration. A relevant threshold happens when the pattern complexity is at most , the number of cells in shape . Hence we say that has low complexity with respect to shape if

We call a low complexity configuration if it has low complexity with respect to some finite shape .

1.3 Nivat’s conjecture

The original motivation to this work is the famous conjecture presented by Maurice Nivat in his keynote address for the 25th anniversary of the European Association for Theoretical Computer Science at ICALP 1997. It concerns two-dimensional configurations that have low complexity with respect to a rectangular shape.

Conjecture ([nivat]).

Let be a two-dimensional configuration. If has low complexity with respect to some rectangle then is periodic.

The conjecture is still open but several partial and related results have been established. The best general bound was proved in [cyrkra] where it was shown that for any rectangle the condition is enough to guarantee that is periodic. This fact can also be proved using the algebraic approach [szabados].

The analogous conjecture in dimensions higher than two fails, as does a similar claim in two dimensions for many other shapes than rectangles [cassaigne]. We return to Nivat’s conjecture and our results on this problem in Section 2.

1.4 Basic concepts of symbolic dynamics

Let be a finite pattern of shape . The set of configurations that have in domain is called the cylinder determined by . The collection of cylinders is a base of a compact topology on , the prodiscrete topology. The topology is equivalently defined by a metric on where two configurations are close to each other if they agree with each other on a large region around cell – the larger the region the closer they are. Cylinders are clopen in the topology: they are both open and closed.

A subset of is called a subshift if it is closed in the topology and closed under translations. By a compactness argument, every configuration that is not in contains a finite pattern that prevents it from being in : no configuration that contains is in . We can then as well define subshifts using forbidden patterns: given a set of finite patterns we define

the set of configurations that do not contain any of the patterns in . Set is a subshift, and every subshift is for some . If for some finite then is a subshift of finite type (SFT).

In this work we are interested in subshifts that have low pattern complexity. For a subshift (or actually for any set of configurations) we define its language to be the set of all finite patterns that appear in some element of , that is, the union of sets over all . For a fixed shape , we analogously define , the union of all over . We say that has low complexity with respect to shape if . For example, in Theorem 7 we fix shape and a small set of at most allowed patterns of shape . Then is a low complexity SFT since and .

The orbit of a configuration is the set of all its translates, and the orbit closure of is the topological closure of its orbit. The orbit closure is a subshift, and in fact it is the intersection of all subshifts that contain . In terms of finite patters, if and only if every finite pattern that appears in appears also in . Of course, the orbit closure of a low complexity configuration is a low complexity subshift.

A configuration is called uniformly recurrent if for every we have . This is equivalent to being a minimal subshift in the sense that it has no proper non-empty subshifts inside it. A classical result by Birkhoff on dynamical systems implies that every non-empty subshift contains a minimal subshift, so there is a uniformly recurrent configuration in every non-empty subshift [birkhoff].

1.5 Algebraic concepts

To use commutative algebra we assume that , i.e., the symbols in the configurations are integers. We also maintain the assumption that is finite. We express a -dimensional configuration as a formal power series over variables where the monomials address cells in a natural manner , and the coefficients of the monomials in the power series are the symbols at the corresponding cells. Using the convenient vector notation we write for the monomial that represents cell . Note that all our power series and polynomials are Laurent as we allow negative as well as positive powers of variables. Now the configuration can be coded as the formal power series

Because is finite, the power series is integral (the coefficients are integers) and finitary (there are only finitely many different coefficients). Henceforth we treat configurations as integral, finitary power series.

Note that the power series are indeed formal: the role of the variables is only to provide the position information on the grid. We may sum up two power series, or multiply a power series with a polynomial, but we never plug in any values in the variables. Multiplying a power series by a monomial simply adds to the exponents of all monomials, thus producing the power series of the translated configuration . Hence the configuration is -periodic if and only if , that is, if and only if , the zero power series. Thus we can express the periodicity of a configuration in terms of its annihilation under the multiplication with a difference binomial . Very naturally then we introduce the annihilator ideal

containing all the polynomials that annihilate . Here we use the notation for the set of Laurent polynomials with complex coefficients. Note that is indeed an ideal of the Laurent polynomial ring .

Our first observation relates the low complexity assumption to annihilators. Namely, it is easy to see using elementary linear algebra that any low complexity configuration has at least some non-trivial annihilators:

Lemma 1 ([icalp]).

Let be a low complexity configuration. Then contains a non-zero polynomial.

One of the main results of [icalp] states that if a configuration is annihilated by a non-zero polynomial (e.g., due to low complexity) then it is automatically annihilated by a product of difference binomials.

Theorem 2 ([icalp]).

Let be a configuration annihilated by some non-zero polynomial. Then there exist pairwise linearly independent such that

Note that if then the configuration is -periodic. Otherwise, for , annihilation by can be considered a form of generalized periodicity.

In the two-dimensional setting we find it sometimes more convenient to work with the periodizer ideal

that contains those two-variate Laurent polynomials whose product with configuration is two-periodic. Clearly also is an ideal of the Laurent polynomial ring , and we have . In the two-dimensional case we have a very good understanding of the structure of the ideals and , see Theorems 8 and 9 in Section 3.

2 Contributions to Nivat’s conjecture

In [icalp] we reported an asymptotic result on Nivat’s conjecture. The complete proof appeared in [icalpfull]. Recall that the Nivat’s conjecture claims – taking the contrapositive of the original statement – that every non-periodic configuration has high complexity with respect to every rectangle. Our result states that this indeed holds for all sufficiently large rectangles:

Theorem 3 ([icalp, icalpfull]).

Let be a two-dimensional configuration that is not periodic. Then holds for all but finitely many rectangles .

Recall that Theorem 2 gives for a low complexity configuration an annihilator of the form . If then is periodic, so it is interesting to consider the cases of . Szabados proved in[szabados] that Nivat’s conjecture holds in the case . Note that this case is equivalent to being the sum of two periodic configurations [icalp].

Theorem 4 ([szabados]).

Let be a two-dimensional configuration that has low complexity with respect to some rectangle. If is the sum of two periodic configurations then itself is periodic.

We have also considered other types of configurations. Particularly interesting are uniformly recurrent configurations since they occur in all non-empty subshifts. Recently we proved that they satisfy Nivat’s conjecture, even when rectangles are generalized to other discrete convex shapes. We call shape convex if for some convex set . In particular, every rectangle is convex.

Theorem 5 ([focs]).

Two-dimensional uniformly recurrent configuration that has low complexity with respect to a finite discrete convex shape is periodic.

The presence of uniformly recurrent configurations in subshifts then directly yields the following corollary.

Theorem 6 ([focs]).

Let be a non-empty two-dimensional subshift that has low complexity with respect to a finite discrete convex shape . Then contains a periodic configuration. In particular, the orbit closure of a configuration that has low complexity with respect to contains a periodic configuration.

Note that the periodic element in the orbit closure of means that contains arbitrarily large periodic regions.

The existence of periodic elements provides us with an algorithm to determine if a given low complexity SFT is empty. This is a classical argument by Hao Wang [wang]: There is a semi-algorithm for non-emptyness of arbitrary SFTs, and there is a semi-algorithm for the existence of a periodic configuration in a two-dimensional SFT. The latter semi-algorithm is based on the fact that if a two-dimensional SFT contains a periodic configuration then it also contains a two-periodic configuration, and these can be effectively enumerated and tested. Now, since we know that a two-dimensional SFT that has low complexity with respect to a convex shape is either empty or contains a periodic configuration, the two semi-algorithms together yield an algorithm to test emptyness.

Theorem 7 ([focs]).

There is an algorithm that – given a set of at most patterns over a two-dimensional convex shape – determines whether there exists a configuration such that .

3 Line polynomials and the structure of the annihilator ideal

For a polynomial , we call its support. A line polynomial is a polynomial with all its terms aligned on the same line: is a line polynomial in direction if and only if contains at least two elements and . (Note that this definition differs slightly from the one in [icalp, icalpfull] where the line containing the non-zero terms was not required to go through the origin. The definitions are the same up to multiplication by a monomial, i.e. a translation.) Multiplying a configuration by a line polynomial is a one-dimensional process: different discrete lines in the direction of the line polynomial get multiplied independently of each other.

Difference binomials are line polynomials so the special annihilator provided by Theorem 2 is a product of line polynomials. Annihilation by a difference binomial means periodicity – and this fact generalizes to any line polynomial: a configuration that is annihilated by a line polynomial in direction is -periodic for some . This is due to the fact that the line polynomial annihilator specifies a linear recurrence along the discrete lines in direction .

The annihilator and the periodizer ideals of a configuration have particularly nice forms in the two-dimensional setting. Recall that is the principal ideal generated by Laurent polynomial . It turns out that a two-dimensional periodizer ideal is a principal ideal generated by a product of line polynomials.

Theorem 8 (adapted from [icalpfull]).

Let be a two-dimensional configuration with a non-trivial annihilator. Then for a product of some line polynomials .

By merging line polynomials in the same directions we can choose in the theorem above so that they are in pairwise linearly independent directions. In this case , the number of line polynomial factors, only depends on . We denote and call it the order of . If then is periodic, and Theorem 4 states that the Nivat’s conjecture is true among configurations of order two.

Theorem 8 directly implies a simple structure on the annihilator ideal: any annihilation of factors through the two-periodic configuration .

Theorem 9 ([icalpfull]).

Let be a two-dimensional configuration with a non-trivial annihilator. Then where are line polynomials and is the annihilator ideal of the two-periodic configuration .

As pointed out above, if is annihilated by a line polynomial then is periodic. The structure of and allows us to generalize this to other annihilators. If a two-dimensional configuration is annihilated (or even periodized) by a polynomial without any line polynomial factors then it follows from Theorem 8 that is generated by polynomial , that is, itself is already two-periodic. Similarly, if contains a polynomial whose line polynomial factors are all in a common direction then is generated by a line polynomial in this direction, implying that has a line polynomial annihilator and is therefore periodic. Such situations have come up in the literature under the theme of covering codes on the grid [Axenovich].

Example 1.

Consider the problem of placing identical broadcasting antennas on the grid in such a way that each cell that does not contain an antenna receives broadcast from exactly antennas and every cell containing an antenna receives exactly broadcasts. Assume that is the shape of coverage by an antenna at the origin. Let us represent this broadcast range as the Laurent polynomial . Let be a configuration over where we interpret as the presence of an antenna in cell . Now, is a solution to the antenna placement problem if and only if is the power series where is the constant one power series . Indeed, has values and in cells containing and not containing an antenna, respectively. In other words, is a valid placement of antennas if and only if multiplying with polynomial results in the two-periodic configuration . If has no line polynomial factors then we know that this condition forces to be two-periodic. For example, if so that each antenna only broadcasts to its own cell and the four neighboring cells, then implies two-periodicity of any solution. ∎

4 Low complexity configurations in algebraic subshifts

In [karimoutot] we considered low complexity configurations in algebraic subshifts where the alphabet is a finite field . As Lemma 1 works as well in this setup, we have that every low complexity configuration is annihilated by a non-zero polynomial . We then have that is an element of the algeraic subshift of all configurations over that are annihilated by . So, to prove Nivat’s conjecture it is enough to prove it for elements of algebraic subshifts. Clearly is of finite type, defined by forbidden patterns of shape . We remark that the theory of this type of algebraically defined subshifts is well developed, see for example [schmidt].

Example 2.

Let . The Ledrappier subshift (also known as the 3-dot system) is for . Elements of are the space-time diagrams of the binary state XOR cellular automaton that adds to the state of each cell modulo 2 the state of its left neighbor. ∎

While Lemma 1 works just fine over finite fields , Theorem 2 does not: it is not true that every element of every algebraic subshift would be annihilated by a product of difference polynomials. However, configurations over can be also considered as configurations over , without making calculations modulo . If a configuration over has low complexity then it also has low complexity as a configuration over , and thus in it has a special annihilator provided by Theorem 2. Now, considering all calculations modulo we see that this special annihilator is also an annihilator over . We conclude that even over , every low complexity configuration has an annihilator that is a product of difference binomials.

Example 3.

Let be a low complexity configuration in the Ledrappier subshift of Example 2. It is then annihilated by and by some that is a product of difference binomials. Because does not have line polynomial factors while all irreducible factors of are line polynomials, we have that and do not have any common factors. Replacing by in , we can entirely eliminate variable from , obtaining a new annihilator of having no occurrence of variable . This annihilator is non-zero because and do not have common factors, which implies that is horizontally periodic. We can repeat the same reasoning in the vertical direction, obtaining that is two periodic. ∎

The reasoning in the example above can be generalized to other algebraic subshifts.

Theorem 10 ([karimoutot]).

Let be a low complexity configuration of an algebraic subshift .

  • If has no line polynomial factors then is two-periodic.

  • If all line polynomial factors of are in a common direction then is periodic.

Note that in the theorem there is no assumption about the low complexity shape , so the applicability of the theorem is not restricted to rectangles or convex shapes.

5 Conclusions and Perspectives

There remains many open questions for future study. Obviously, the full version of Nivat’s conjecture is still unsolved. Our Theorem 5 suggests that perhaps periodicity is forced by the low complexity condition not only on rectangles but on other convex shapes as well, as conjectured by Julien Cassaigne in [cassaigne]. In his examples of non-periodic low complexity configurations, the low complexity shape is always non-convex. Moreover, all two-dimensional low complexity configurations that we know consist of periodic sublattices [cassaigne, karimoutot]

. For example, even lattice cells may form a configuration that is horizontally but not vertically periodic while the odd cells may have a vertical but no horizontal period. The interleaved non-periodic configuration may have low complexity with respect to a scatted shape

that only sees cells of equal parity. We wonder if there exist any low complexity configurations without a periodic sublattice structure.

Theorem 4 proves Nivat’s conjecture for configurations of order two. However, case is special in the sense that is then a sum of periodic configurations, that is, finitary power series. In general, any configuration with a non-trivial annihilator is a sum of periodic power series [icalp], but already when these power series may be necessarily non-finitary [cai]. It seems then that proving Nivat’s conjecture for configurations of order three would reflect the general case better than the order two case. We also remark that proving Nivat’s conjecture (for all convex shapes) would render the results of Section 2 obsolete.

There are also very interesting questions concerning general low complexity SFTs. By Theorem 6, a two-dimensional SFT that is low complexity with respect to a convex shape contains periodic configurations. Might this be true for non-convex shapes as well ? If so, analogously to Theorem 7, this would yield and algorithm to decide emptyness of general low complexity SFTs. What about higher dimensions ? We do not know of any aperiodic low complexity SFT in any dimension of the space. The following example recalls a family of particularly interesting low complexity SFTs.

Example 4.

A -dimensional cluster tile is a finite subset , and a co-tiler is a subset such that . Visually, gives positions where copies of tiles can be placed so that every cell gets covered by exactly one tile. Looking at the situation from an arbitrary covered cell , we see that is a co-tiler of if and only if the set contains precisely one element of , for every . Representing a co-tiler as the indicator configuration if and if , we have that the set of valid co-tilers for tile is a low complexity SFT: The only allowed patterns of shape are those that contain single , and there are such patterns.

The periodic cluster tiling problem asks whether every tile that has a co-tiler also has a periodic co-tiler [LagariasWang, Szegedy]. This is a special case of the more general question on arbitrary low complexity SFTs discussed above. The periodic cluster tiling problem was recently answered affirmatively in the two-dimensional case [bhattacharya]. In [icalp] we gave a simple algebraic proof in any number of dimensions for the case – originally handled in [Szegedy] – where is a prime number. ∎

Finally, the structure of the annihilator ideal is not known in dimension higher than two. We wonder how Theorem 9 might generalize to the three-dimensional setting.

References