Explicit shading strategies for repeated truthful auctions

05/01/2018 ∙ by Marc Abeille, et al. ∙ Criteo berkeley college 0

With the increasing use of auctions in online advertising, there has been a large effort to study seller revenue maximization, following Myerson's seminal work, both theoretically and practically. We take the point of view of the buyer in classical auctions and ask the question of whether she has an incentive to shade her bid even in auctions that are reputed to be truthful, when aware of the revenue optimization mechanism. We show that in auctions such as the Myerson auction or a VCG with reserve price set as the monopoly price, the buyer who is aware of this information has indeed an incentive to shade. Intuitively, by selecting the revenue maximizing auction, the seller introduces a dependency on the buyers' distributions in the choice of the auction. We study in depth the case of the Myerson auction and show that a symmetric equilibrium exists in which buyers shade non-linearly what would be their first price bid. They then end up with an expected payoff that is equal to what they would get in a first price auction with no reserve price. We conclude that a return to simple first price auctions with no reserve price or at least non-dynamic anonymous ones is desirable from the point of view of both buyers, sellers and increasing transparency.

READ FULL TEXT VIEW PDF
POST COMMENT

Comments

There are no comments yet.

Authors

page 1

page 2

page 3

page 4

This week in AI

Get the week's most popular data science and artificial intelligence research sent straight to your inbox every Saturday.

1. Introduction

Billions of auctions are run worldwide everyday. One of the main supplier of such auctions is the online advertising market (Allouah and Besbes, 2017; Balseiro et al., 2015; Amin et al., 2012). Ad slots are sold to advertisers by a publisher, typically a web site, following more or less explicit mechanisms, i.e., a type of auctions with specific rules. Those auctions take place on platforms known as “ad exchanges” (Muthukrishnan, 2009).

Maybe the most common types of auctions used in this setting are the classical second price auctions with or without reserve prices as they are reputed to be truthful (it is dominant to bid the true valuation) and even optimal for identical bidders (Myerson, 1981; Riley and Samuelson, 1981). Auction theory has been developed for several decades (and several Nobel prices were granted for those breakthroughs). As a consequence, optimal strategies of the bidders (when they exist) and revenue maximizing mechanisms are almost perfectly understood.

However, one of the crucial working assumption is that the seller must know the distribution of valuations of the bidders to tune optimally her mechanism (for instance by setting the right reserve price). In practice though, this assumption is obviously not satisfied (Wilson, 1987). On the other hand, in most real life applications, such as online advertising, auctions between a single publisher and the same advertisers are not run only once, but several hundred thousand times each day. As a consequence, the seller has access to an incredibly large amount of bids from each bidder for more or less equivalent goods. So one trend of research is to learn the optimal mechanisms from the past sequence of bids, assuming that they truthfully represent the valuations of the bidders (Cesa-Bianchi et al., 2013; Fu et al., 2013; Ostrovsky and Schwarz, 2011; Cole and Roughgarden, 2014; Amin et al., 2015; Kanoria and Nazerzadeh, 2014; Dhangwatnotai et al., 2015; Blum et al., 2015; Medina and Mohri, 2014; Amin et al., 2014; Morgenstern and Roughgarden, 2016; Chawla et al., 2007; Daskalakis and Syrgkanis, 2016).

The motivation behind this traditional assumption is that the seller is only choosing incentive compatible auctions such as Vickrey auctions. Therefore, since in a one shot second price auctions it is optimal to bid one’s own valuations, the seller can safely expect to observe the past valuations of the buyer, and hence an approximation of her distribution of valuations. Even if computing the optimal auction of Myerson might be complicated, as it needs an almost number of samples, there exist approximatively optimal auctions (Hartline and Roughgarden, 2009; Fu et al., 2013; Hartline, 2009) requiring a much more reasonable amount of data.

Our starting point is the following claim. If the seller uses data acquired on past auctions to update the mechanism (say, to fix dynamically the reserve price) then the repeated mechanism might no longer be truthful. Intuitively, this is rather clear. Assume that the reserve price in the second price auction of a seller is determined by her past bids. By bidding untruthfully (even in Vickrey auctions!), the bidder might lower drastically her reserve price, at a small cost of lost auctions. As a result, her bids might actually clear the new reserve price more often than with truthful bids.

We actually prove this intuition that several mechanisms known to be truthful in the one shot case are no longer truthful in the repeated setting. Assuming symmetrical bidders and a seller that myopically designs a Myerson auction with respect to the past sequence of bids (in effect assuming they were equal to the valuations), we prove that a symmetric equilibrium enforce the same outcome than second price auctions without reserve prices !

Actually, our results do not rely on the finite sample setting that has received a lot of attention recently (both from the seller, but also on the bidder point of view (McAfee, 2011; Weed et al., 2016)). We will directly assume that a strategy of a bidder is a modification (or a function) of her true valuation, that the seller observes the distribution of bids, from which she computes reserve prices. The payoff of a strategy (a.k.a a modifying or shading function) will therefore be computed as the expected gain of the auctions run with all those parameters. Although interesting, putting an extra layer of learning over datasets of finite sample size is not necessarily to convey our main messages.

The paper is organized as follows. We introduce the model in Section 2. In Section 3, we prove the claim that repeated “one-shot truthful” auctions (for several widely used types of auction) are no longer truthful by exhibiting a simple strategy that dominates truthful bidding. We investigate in detail the Myerson auction in Section 4, where we prove that a symmetric equilibrium enforces the same outcome as second price auctions without reserve prices. The Appendix contains more technical results, reminders and proofs of some lemmas.

2. Setting

We consider independent bidders with distributions of valuation participating to repeated independent auctions: the values of bidder in the different auctions are i.i.d., drawn from . We consider only stationary strategies, i.e., the bidder applies a function mapping her value to a bid, and we denote by the set of strategy profiles. We will assume the to be increasing – i.e. the higher the value, the higher the bid. We denote the resulting distributions of bids – i.e. is the distribution of where is drawn from . Especially, as the are increasing, we can have

Another quantity of interest in auction studies, only depending on the distribution of a r.v. with distribution , is the virtual value of a bidder and the related hazard rate . We can notice we have the following link between the virtual values of and :

(1)

Hence, up to solving the ODE (1), we can manipulate equivalently the bidder’s strategy , the virtual value at value exposed to the seller or the corresponding hazard rate .

2.1. Revenue Maximizing Auctions

With the widespread use of auctions in online advertising markets, there has been an extensive work about characterizing and estimating revenue-maximizing auctions in different settings. More recently, some focus has been put on practical estimation of such auctions and derivation of approximations simpler to optimize, such as boosted second-price auctions

(Golrezaei et al., 2017) or second-price with monopoly reserve price (Roughgarden and Wang, 2016).

More formally,

being the space of probability distributions over the K bidders, the seller chooses a class of auctions

consisting in a pair of functions (allocation rule) and (payment rule). Here, is the probability for bidder to win when bidders submit and the corresponding expected payment. We denote

As she only observes bid distributions , the seller picks the revenue maximizing auction,

Under incentive compatibility and individual rationality, the expected payment of bidder is

see, e.g., (Myerson, 1981). The seller does not observe but only , and we will always assume that she is not strategic: she optimizes her revenue as if she was observing the valuations, i.e.,

2.2. Examples of mechanisms, allocations and payment rules.

We introduce in this section some of the widely-used (and truthful) auctions mechanisms that we will consider.

Vickrey-Clarke-Groves (VCG) mechanisms are second price auctions with non-anonymous reserve prices, i.e., different reserve prices to different bidder. Then is the set of all possible reserve prices. Different allocation rule exist: an item can be allocated to the highest bidder amongst all those that have cleared their reserve price, or to no one if no reserve price is cleared. We will call it the eager version of Vickrey-Clarke-Groves (VCG) mechanism.

Another allocation rule dictates to allocate the item to the higher bidder, if she has cleared her reserve price, and to no one otherwise. This version of the VCG mechanism will be called lazy (with anonymous reserve prices, eager and lazy versions coincide).

Computations of optimal non-anonymous reserve prices suffer from being NP-hard (Paes Leme et al., 2016) and even APX-hard(Roughgarden and Wang, 2016). However, (Roughgarden and Wang, 2016) also proved that using the monopoly price as reserve price in a VCG auction leads to a 2-approximation of the Myerson auction. It also led (Paes Leme et al., 2016) to prove that the lazy version of VCG admit the monopoly price as optimal reserve price and is a 2-approximation of the VCG with optimal reserve prices.

Myerson type of auctions allocate the item to the highest non-negative (assuming there is one) virtual value of the bids and to no one otherwise. The payment of the winner is the smallest winning bid, i.e., . The Myerson auction maximizes the expected seller revenue at the equilibrium, at least if virtual values are increasing. Moreover, in the symmetric case where the distribution of valuations is the same for all bidder, then Myerson auction coincides with the VCG auction with reserve price .

A Myerson-type of auctions would follow the same rules except that any non-linear, increasing transformation can be used instead of the actual virtual value. In that case, can be either the set of such transformations, or the set of transformations and non-anonymous reserve prices.

Boosted second price auctions. In boosted second price auctions (Golrezaei et al., 2017), the seller chooses parameters and boosts the bid of bidder by while keeping a reserve price . As a consequence, a bid is transformed into a virtual one through the formula . Then is the set of affine transformations of the bids, or subsets thereof.

Boosted second price auctions actually correspond to Myerson-type auctions if the distributions of valuations belong to the family of Generalized Pareto (GP) distributions. We refer to Section B in the Appendix for more details on the class of GP distributions. Approximating the actual distribution of valuations by a GP, and computing the optimal mechanism w.r.t. theses approximations can actually be simpler than the optimal Myerson auction (Golrezaei et al., 2017).

Other mechanisms: posted price, first price, etc. There exist many other auction mechanisms that are more or less equivalent to one of the former under specific assumptions. For instance, in posted price auctions, the seller fixes a price and the item is sold to one bidder (or all of them) whose valuation is higher than the price. Notice that posting price is equivalent to VCG if only one buyer participates in the auctions.

Computing and learning the optimal posted price can also be done in an online fashion and/or using finite number of samples (Kleinberg and Leighton, 2003; Blum et al., 2003; Bubeck et al., 2017)

In first price auctions, the item is sold to the highest bidder (or potentially the bidder with the highest virtual bids, or the highest bidder above his reserve price) but with the simple payment rule: the highest bidder simply pays his winning (virtual) bids. Revenue equivalence principle (Krishna, 2009)

states that these auctions are, at the equilibrium, more or less equivalent, but the reputed truthfulness (hence simple “optimal strategies”) of second-price auction make these type of auctions less common, for the moment at least

(Sluis, 2017).

2.3. Strategic Buyer Problem under Seller Revenue Maximization

In the literature, the study of revenue maximization is done under the assumption that buyers bid truthfully even if they are aware of the revenue maximization mechanism. This can be motivated in certain settings where the seller faces repeated auctions, but buyers change from auction to auction (as on EBay). When the buyers are interacting repeatedly with the same seller and if they know the mechanism, such as dynamic reserve prices, it is quite easy to exhibit examples proving that incentive compatibility is lost. Yet, state-of-art comes short of providing the bidders with a better strategy than being truthful. This lack of understanding of the buyers strategy in presence of dynamic reserve prices is arguably one of the major factor for the shift of the market towards first price auctions (Sluis, 2017).

We are only considering stationary strategies and assuming that auctions are infinitely repeated and undiscounted, hence the pay-off of bidder , whose valuation is and bids , is defined by

(2)

where

is the vector of bids send by the bidders.

Then, supposing the seller is choosing the revenue maximization auctions within a given class of truthful auctions (e.g. setting different prices, various boosted second price auctions etc…), the question is whether it’s still in the interest of the bidders to remain truthful. In light of the seller’s optimizing behavior (and because we consider infinitely undiscounted repeated auctions), player faces the following optimization problem. Given the distribution of valuations and the bidding strategies of other bidders , solve

(3)

Depending on the auction class , the bidders may not be able to derive optimal strategies from (3) and it is not clear whether they always have incentive to bid untruthfully. Hence, we propose in Section 3 to study if several auctions considered in revenue optimization are robust to a simple shading scheme in the context of a bidder optimizing (3). Then, in Section 4, we compute the equilibrium strategy of (3) for Myerson auctions with symmetric bidders.

3. Loss of Incentive Compatibility.

To get a sense of whether revenue optimization completely breaks the truthfulness, we first study whether several common auctions used for revenue optimization are robust to a very simple modification of strategy: a linear shading of the truthful bid – i.e. . Then, the relationship between virtual values and hazard rate simplifies,

We are going to consider the simple setting where only bidder is being strategic. The assumption of the other bidders being truthful is not a strong restriction as we do not consider the bidders to be symmetric, hence a bidder bidding truthfully under a distribution of value can also be seen as a bidder following a strategy under a distribution of value .

A mild technical point related to the issue of support might need to be raised: to the left of the support of we can define the hazard rate as and hence is equal to there. In particular, if and don’t have the same support.

3.1. Myerson Auction

For simplicity we write . In this case we know exactly the strategy of the seller, so we can directly re-write the payment of .

The expected payoff under linear shading assuming that the other bidders fixed their strategy is

The following lemma states that bidder has incentives to deviate from truthful bidding – i.e. to choose . To support this claim, we just need to prove that at .

Lemma 3.1 ().

Suppose that is differentiable and that on . Then

In other words, bidder has an incentive to shade his/her bid in this case.

The conditions of Lemma 3.1 are satisfied when is linear, which happens when has a generalized Pareto distribution. The condition is also satisfied for convex which is not of great interest in the current context.

Proof.

Recall that

Let us call and ; let be its density. Then

Taking the derivative of this quantity with respect to and splitting the expectation in two, we get

Then, we recognize the expected payment (see (Myerson, 1981)) to get and then by definition of the expected payment,

We now focus on the first term. We note that is the density of evaluated at . So rewriting the expectation as an integral and using , we get, after using Fubini,

We can now compare and , term by term. We first note that

This inequality is strict on a set of measure non-zero in our setup, so strict inequality passes to expectations. Under the assumption we made on we have by definition

Then we obtain that and in fact when we have strict inequalities in the above two displays on a common set on non-zero measure. ∎

Though we do not need symmetry of the bidders’ value distribution, we start by a few examples assuming it for concreteness. We recall that if is the cdf of , in the case where we have symmetric bidders.

Example of uniform [0,1] distributions: In this case, on [0,1] and . Also, . Then, using for the instance the representation of the derivative of appearing in the proof of Lemma 3.1, we have

Hence, each user has an incentive to shade their bid. We note that the derivative goes to 0 as (see also Fig.1 right side), which can be interpreted as saying that as the number of users grows, each user has less and less incentive to shade. We can also observe on Fig.1 (left side) that the difference between the payoff at optimal shading and the payoff without shading – – decreases with . Indeed, when grows, the natural level of competition between the bidders makes the revenue optimization mechanisms (e.g. dynamic reserve price) less useful. Logically, being strategic against it in such case does not help much. For very few bidders, the contrary happens. For , we even observe that the optimal strategy is to bid with a shading of to force a price close to while still winning with probability – when one is beating his reserve and the opponent is not beating his, with the result of almost doubling the payoff.

Figure 1. Myerson auction : Expected payoff and its derivative for one bidder with linear shading There are bidders with values , only one of them is strategic. On the left hand side, we present a plot of the expected payoff of the strategic bidder for several values of . On the right hand side, we present the derivative taken at the truthful bid ().

In conclusion, we observed that Myerson auction is not immune to deviations for a large number of distributions (generalized Pareto). Even a linear shading can increase substantially the payoff of the bidder at the expense of the seller’s revenue. As a corollary, the boosted second price auction incurs the same issue as they are equivalent to Myerson auction for generalized Pareto distributions. Now, we aim at extending these results to other simple of auctions proposed in the context of seller revenue optimization.

3.2. VCG with Revenue Optimization

In this section, we study the robustness of eager and lazy VCG auction with monopoly price to linear shading of one bidder. All the computation are very similar for both, differing only by some initial definitions. We denote the VCG auction with monopoly reserve price . Then, the expected payoff of bidder is

Now, considering that all bidders but are bidding truthfully and bidder submit bids , – i.e. – we obtain the following lemma,

Lemma 3.2 ().

For the VCG auction (either eager or lazy) with monopoly reserve price,

In other words, bidder has an incentive to shade his/her bid even individually.

Proof.

The same proof holds for both eager and lazy, just by using different definition for . We define for the eager one and for the lazy one. Define and its density. Assume that bidder shades his bids linearly, and rewrite

Let us compute the partial derivatives of the payoff at .

As before, we denote that . Then, similarly as before, we use Fubini argument to obtain

We can now compare and , term by term. We first note that

This inequality is strict on a set of measure non-zero, so . ∎

Figure 2. VCG lazy : Expected payoff and its derivative for one bidder with linear shading There are bidders with values , only one of them is strategic. On the left hand side, we present a plot of the expected payoff of the strategic bidder for several values of . On the right hand side, we present the derivative taken at the truthful bid ().

We can observe on Figure 2 a very similar results for the lazy VCG as on Figure 1 in the Myerson case. There is an incentive to shade the bids, decreasing with the number of bidders. However, the optimal shading is less aggressive than in Myerson case, resulting in a smaller increment of the bidder’s payoff. Our intuition is that the class of auctions over which the seller maximizes his revenue is smaller than in Myerson’s case, providing less leverage to the bidders to be strategic. Investigating the link between the complexity of (e.g. pseudo-dimension) and the gain for the bidders in being strategic is definitely of interest for future research.

4. Further results for the Myerson auction

4.1. Formulation of the problem

4.1.1. Differential equation formulation

We go back to Myerson auction where bidder 1 shades her bid by bidding , for a function to be determined later, instead of her value .

Let be the virtual value function associated with the distribution of

(in this section we identify a random variable with its distribution, by a slight abuse of notation). We call

the cumulative distribution function of

, where is the bid of bidder , and is the virtual value function associated with the distribution of this bid. We assume as before that bidder 1 faces other bidders for a total of bidders involved in the auction. We call and the associated cumulative distribution function. We assume as before that all bidders are independent. In this case, it is clear that

. Of course, this cdf has a jump discontinuity at 0 when

.

Recall that in the Myerson auction, the expected payment of bidder 1 when she bids using is

See (Krishna, 2009), p. 67 and (Roughgarden, 2016) for details. In the Myerson auction, the expected payoff of bidder 1 when she shades through is therefore

Suppose that , where is small and is a function. Let . We denote the corresponding virtual value function by .

We have (see Lemma A.1 in the Appendix) if we differentiate with respect to and hence take a directional derivative for in the direction of , under mild conditions on ,

(4)

where is such that and . We note that and when .

In the work below, we naturally seek a shading function such that these directional derivatives are equal to 0. We will therefore be interested in particular in functions such that , when . The second term in our equation has intuitively to do with the event where the other bidders are discarded for not beating their reserve price. As we will see below, we can sometimes ignore this term, for instance when an equilibrium strategy exists which amounts to canceling the reserve prices.

Let us first present some intermediary results to get symmetric equilibrium result among others.

4.1.2. Key ODEs and consequences

As before, we call a non-negative random variable representing the distribution of values of bidder 1 with density . For simplicity in defining virtual values we assume that on the support111Taking care of the case where can take the value 0 at a few points introduces artificial technical problems that are not particularly hard to solve but would obscure the flow of our argument. of .

Lemma 4.1 ().

Suppose , where is increasing and differentiable. If , we have

(5)

Furthermore, if for some and a function we have

then

(6)
Interpretation

Informally, the previous result says that it would be very easy for bidder 1 to shade her bid in such a way that the virtual value of her bid , i.e. , be any function of her value she chooses.

A simple consequence of Lemma 4.1 is the following result, which pertains directly to non-linear shading strategies.

Lemma 4.2 ().

Let be an increasing function. Call the support of . Assume that on .  Then, defined as

(7)

is increasing and differentiable on the support of .

In particular, if , we have, for ,

The proof of these technical but not difficult lemmas are in the Appendix, Subsection A.2.

4.2. The case of symmetric bidders

Theorem 4.3 ().

Consider an auction with independent and symmetric bidders, having value distribution represented by the random variable .

In the Myerson auction, a symmetric equilibrium strategy for the bidders is to shade their bids by a function that satisfies

where is their symmetric equilibrium first price bid in a first price auction with no reserve price.

A solution of this equation is

With this strategy, the bidders’ expected payoffs are the same as what they would get in a first price auction with no reserve price. In particular, it is strictly greater than their expected payoffs had they bid truthfully.

Discussion

The intuition behind this result is quite clear. In the Myerson auction, the expected payoff of any given bidder is the same as that of a first price auction where her bids have been transformed through the use of her virtual value function. We call the corresponding pseudo-bids virtualized bids. Hence, if the bidders can bid in such a way that their “virtualized” bids are equal to their symmetric equilibrium first price bids, the situation is completely equivalent to a first price auction. And hence their equilibrium strategy in virtualized bid space should be the strategy they use in a standard first price auction with no reserve price.

Our theorem shows that by adopting such a strategy symmetric bidders can avoid facing a non-zero reserve price. Furthermore, Lemmas 4.1 and 4.2

show that it is easy for bidders to shade in such a way that their virtualized bids are equal to any increasing function of their value they choose. Also, this shading is specific to each bidder: the corresponding ordinary differential equations do not involve the other bidders. As such it is also quite easy to implement.

Nonetheless, the shading is quite counter-intuitive at first, since bidders may end up bidding higher than their value (for instance if their value is 0). Their payments are however made in terms of virtualized bids, at least in expectation. And of course, in terms of virtualized bids, nothing is counter-intuitive: everything has been done so that their virtualized bids are equal to their first price bids, which are less than their values.

Proof.

We first investigate properties of and in symmetric situations and then verify, as is classical (see (Krishna, 2009), Chapter 2), that our proposed solution is indeed an equilibrium.

Suppose the bidders shade using the shading function . Let us call , when . Note that all ’s have the same distribution in symmetric equilibrium, which we call .

In a symmetric equilibrium, everybody will use this shading. Recall that the key relation was

Preliminaries 1: Symmetric situation: property of and : If , with increasing,

Therefore,

If are independent and are using this strategy, we have for ,

So the key relation

can now be re-written as

Preliminaries 2: Connection with first price auctions
We recognize here the equation for defining the shading strategy in a first price auction with no reserve price (see Krishna (2009), Chapter 2). We can also solve this equation in a very simple way. Indeed, the most general solution of this differential equation is just

Taking

we find a solution that is increasing, with for . Of course, can be reinterpreted as

where is the maximum bid of bidder 1’s competitors in the auction. This of course is nothing but a symmetric equilibrium first price bid in the symmetric case with no reserve price, see (Krishna, 2009), p. 15.

Verification argument Equipped with the results we derived above, the last step of the proof is just a verification argument. We note that is an increasing function of . Furthermore, if is a solution of

such that

we have seen in Lemma 4.2 that is increasing under our assumptions when is increasing as is the case here. Also for and if . ( is the right end point of the support of .)

We conclude that our function is increasing.

We need to verify that the problem we are dealing with is regular, so that the payoff of the Myerson auction is indeed what we announced and in particular, no ironing is necessary (see Myerson (1981) or Toikka (2011)) . Almost by definition, we have, if ,

Since is increasing, so is ; and since is increasing, so is . We conclude that is increasing and so the design problem for the seller receiving is regular.

Now as we are in the symmetric case, if our adversaries use this strategy, bidder 1’s opposition in virtual value space is . For this last equality we have used the well-known and easy to verify fact that with probability 1. So the distribution of is continuous, it has no discontinuity at 0. In particular, for the functional derivative of our payoff we have, in the notation of Subsection 4.1

Now we have done everything so that with as above (and )

Of course the same reasoning applies to the other bidders. To finish the equilibrium proof, we note that the expected payoff of the bidder shading her bid as described above is the same as what she would get in a first price auction with no reserve price. Using the revenue equivalence principle (see (Krishna, 2009), Chapter 3), this is also what she would get in a second price auction with no reserve price. Of course, the standard Myerson auction where bidders are symmetric and bid truthfully amounts to performing a second price auction with reserve price set at the monopoly price . The expected payoff of the bidders for this latter auction is clearly strictly less than that in the second price auction with no reserve price. We conclude that the expected payoff of the symmetric bidders using the strategy described above is strictly greater than what they would have gotten had they bid truthfully. ∎

4.3. The case of one strategic bidder

The case of one strategic bidder is also of interest, and motivated by the different nature of the various bidders involved in online advertising auctions. Recent work on boosted second price auctions (Golrezaei et al., 2017) was in part motivated by the desire to account for this diversity, between for instance what these authors call brand bidders and retargeting bidders, and also to simplify the implementation of the Myerson auction. Recall that (Golrezaei et al., 2017) propose to effectively linearize the virtual value of the bidders before applying a Myerson-type approach on these “linearly-virtualized” bids.

In this context, distributions with exactly linear virtual value play a particular role. It is easy to show that those distributions are Generalized Pareto (GP) distributions. We refer to (Balseiro et al., 2015) and (Allouah and Besbes, 2017) for their use in the auction context and for pointing out their remarkable simplicity in terms of virtual value computations.

When doing explicit computations or focusing on boosted second price auctions we will naturally also make use of this family of distributions.

4.3.1. General formulation

The problem faced by bidder 1 in the Myerson auction has not changed. She seeks to shade her bid through a mapping , i.e. bid so as to maximize

Nonetheless, two aspects of the problem will now differ from our earlier work: on the one hand , which represents the bid distributions she is facing is now “fixed”, i.e. unaffected by , because the other bidders are non-strategic; on the other hand, the shading function will on occasion be considered to be part of a parametric family. In this case, what was before a directional derivative will then be a simple gradient.

With this in mind, and with a slight overloading of notations (since in the parametric case below is just a gradient), we recall the key relationship

where is such that and . We will be keenly interested in shading functions such that

Indeed, for those ’s, the expectation in our differential will be 0. Hence, computing the differential will be relatively simple and in particular will give us reasonable guesses for and descent directions, even if it does not always give us directly an optimal shading strategy. Furthermore, when is large, the second term fades out, as the probability that no other bidder clear their reserve prices becomes very small.

If we proceed formally, and call, for , (temporarily assuming that this - possibly generalized - functional inverse can be made sense of), we see that solving the previous equation amounts to solving

Lemma 4.1 can of course be brought to bear on this problem. We note that we will be primarily interested in solutions of this equation for ’s such that