Contest Architecture with Public Disclosures

05/27/2019
by   Toomas Hinnosaar, et al.
Hinnosaar
0

I study optimal disclosure policies in sequential contests. A contest designer chooses at which periods to publicly disclose the efforts of previous contestants. I provide results for a wide range of possible objectives for the contest designer. While different objectives involve different trade-offs, I that show that under many circumstances the optimal contest is one of the three basic contest structures widely studied in the literature: simultaneous, first-mover, or sequential contest.

READ FULL TEXT VIEW PDF
POST COMMENT

Comments

There are no comments yet.

Authors

page 1

page 2

page 3

page 4

03/15/2020

Balancing Competing Objectives with Noisy Data: Score-Based Classifiers for Welfare-Aware Machine Learning

While real-world decisions involve many competing objectives, algorithmi...
07/09/2020

The Trade-Offs of Private Prediction

Machine learning models leak information about their training data every...
06/01/2020

Treatment Policy Learning in Multiobjective Settings with Fully Observed Outcomes

In several medical decision-making problems, such as antibiotic prescrip...
06/25/2020

Practical Trade-Offs for the Prefix-Sum Problem

Given an integer array A, the prefix-sum problem is to answer sum(i) que...
02/13/2018

Optimal sequential contests

I study sequential contests where the efforts of earlier players may be ...
01/16/2013

Airport Gate Scheduling for Passengers, Aircraft, and Operation

Passengers' experience is becoming a key metric to evaluate the air tran...
07/13/2020

On the Effectiveness of Tracking and Testing in SEIR Models

We study the effectiveness of tracking and testing in mitigating or supp...
This week in AI

Get the week's most popular data science and artificial intelligence research sent straight to your inbox every Saturday.

1 Introduction

In this paper, I study sequential contests and contest-like economic interactions, where the payoffs increase with participants’ own efforts and decrease with the total effort. For example, lobbyists exert efforts to influence politicians towards desired outcomes. The key regulatory decision is transparency—how much and what kind of information should be collected and disclosed to limit the rent-seeking efforts? A fully transparent lobbying disclosure rule would lead to sequential effort choices, whereas a non-transparent policy leads to independent choices of lobbying efforts.111Different countries have adopted different transparency rules regulating lobbying. For example, in the United States lobbying efforts are all recorded and reported quarterly (Lobbying Disclosure Act, 1995; Honest Leadership and Open Government Act, 2007), whereas in the European Union reporting is arranged on a more voluntary basis and on a yearly frequency (European Transparency Initiative, 2005). Similarly, firms entering oligopolistic markets invest to increase capacity and the market price decreases with the total capacity. Again, transparency plays a crucial role in these investment decisions and it is natural to ask whether the investments should be publicly observable or not. Many economic interactions satisfy the assumptions of the model discussed here, including oligopolies, public goods provision, rent-seeking, research and development, advertising, and sports.

The objective of the contest designer depends on the specific economic problem. Two standard goals discussed in the literature are maximizing the total effort (such as in research and development contests) or minimizing the total effort (as in rent-seeking contests). However, other objectives are more natural in other situations. For example, a school’s objective is not to maximize the average effort, but rather to make sure that all students learn. In fact, the education reform in the US was named the No Child Left Behind Act of 2001. Similarly, in firms where efforts are complementary, it is often important to incentivize the lowest-performing employees, referred to in the business terminology as to as the bottleneck or the weakest link. In welfare economics, there are two standard assumptions. The utilitarian social planner maximizes the total welfare of the participants, whereas the Rawlsian social planner maximizes the lowest utility.

Different objectives lead to different trade-offs and it is natural that the optimal contests in various economic interactions may differ. However, the literature has so far almost exclusively focused on three standard types of contests. First, simultaneous contests, where the players make their choices independently. This is the least informative form of contest, where no efforts are disclosed. It is the most common type of contest considered by the literature, starting with Cournot (1838) in oligopoly theory and Tullock (1967, 1974) in contest theory. The second type of contest that has been extensively studied is the first-mover contest, where a single first-mover chooses the effort first and the rest of the players move simultaneously in the second period. In oligopoly theory it was first analyzed by von Stackelberg (1934) and in contest theory by Dixit (1987).222For literature reviews on dynamic contests, see Konrad (2009) and Vojnović (2015). The third type of contest that has been considered is the sequential contest, where all effort choices are public. Then each player observes all the previous effort choices. Simultaneous contests have been studied by Robson (1990) in the case of large oligopolies, Glazer and Hassin (2000), Hinnosaar (2018), and Kahana and Klunover (2018) in the case of sequential Tullock contests, and Hinnosaar (2018) with more general payoff functions.

The goal of this paper is to understand which types of contests are optimal under different circumstances. On one hand, the paper aims to provide a menu of optimality results that researchers and practitioners could build upon. Perhaps even more importantly, finding contest structures that are optimal under many different sets of assumptions may explain why these types of contests are often used.

The main difficulty in studying sequential contests is tractability. Sequential games with non-quadratic payoffs are typically difficult to solve because best-response functions are non-linear and therefore the standard backward-induction approach leads to increasingly complex expressions. This problem is even more pronounced in contest design, where the goal is to compare all possible contests. In this paper, I build on recent progress in aggregative games (Jensen, 2010; Martimort and Stole, 2012; Acemoglu and Jensen, 2013) and sequential contests (Hinnosaar, 2018, 2019) to overcome the tractability issues.

The main finding of the paper is that under many circumstances the optimal contest is one of the three basic contest structures widely studied in the literature. In particular, I consider minimizing and maximizing eight different objectives: total effort, total welfare, lowest effort, lowest payoff, highest effort, highest payoff, effort inequality, and payoff inequality. I show that nine out of the sixteen maximization problems are solved either by the simultaneous contest or by the sequential contests. With the four out of the remaining five objectives I show that when the number of players is sufficiently large, they are maximized by one of the three basic contest structures mentioned above. I also provide conditions under which the same conclusions hold when the number of players is small. Finally, there is a single exception: minimizing the highest payoff, which typically requires a non-standard contest.333I provide conditions under which it is maximized by a contest where the first two players are moving simultaneously and all the remaining players are arranged sequentially.

The paper contributes to both the contest design and the information design literatures. Earlier papers on contest design have focused on contests with private information and have studied how to arrange contests into subcontests and which prizes to offer to maximize either total effort or highest effort (Glazer and Hassin, 1988; Taylor, 1995; Che and Gale, 2003; Moldovanu and Sela, 2001, 2006; Olszewski and Siegel, 2016; Bimpikis et al., 2019). In this paper, I study contest design with full information. The designer may have different objectives and can choose to disclose less or more information about the players’ efforts. There is growing literature on information design (Kamenica and Gentzkow, 2011; Bergemann and Morris, 2019), which has mostly focused on revealing information about the state of the world or private information. This paper is more in line with recent papers that have also studied disclosure of the actions of other players (Doval and Ely, 2019; Ely and Szydlowski, 2019; Gallice and Monzón, 2019).

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 describes the model. Section 3 provides all results, describing the contests that minimize and maximize eight different objective functions. Section 4 summarizes and concludes. Proofs are in the appendix.

2 Model

There is a finite number players, . Players arrive sequentially and each player chooses effort level at arrival. For a given profile of efforts , the payoff of player is , where denotes the total effort and is the marginal benefit of effort, which is common to all players (I discuss its properties below).

The contest designer chooses points of time at which to publicly disclose the cumulative effort of all players that have already arrived. The disclosure rule is chosen before effort choices and is commonly known. Each such disclosure rule induces a partition of players , where is the set of players arriving between disclosures number and . I refer to the set of players as players arriving in period . Then player observes the cumulative effort of all players arriving in previous periods, , and makes a choice simultaneously with all players arriving in period

. As all players are identical, the disclosure rule is equivalently defined by a vector

, where , so that .444Alternatively, the contest designer’s problem can be interpreted as dividing players between periods.

The marginal benefit function is a strictly decreasing and continuously differentiable function in , where is the saturation point so that . Moreover, I impose two technical assumptions, which are discussed in appendix A. The first assumption guarantees that the best-response functions are well-behaved so that a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium exists and is unique. The second assumption guarantees that the efforts are higher-order strategic substitutes near equilibrium, i.e. higher effort of an earlier-mover discourages efforts by followers both directly and indirectly (through the changed efforts of other players). Both assumptions are satisfied for most applications, including the following three examples.

Example 1 (Sequential Tullock Contest).

Players choose efforts to compete for a prize with value and have constant marginal cost

. The probability of winning is proportional to efforts. The payoffs can be expressed as

, where .

Example 2 (Tragedy of the Commons).

The total amount of resources is and each player chooses private consumption . Marginal benefit of consumption is linearly decreasing in the total consumption, i.e. .555This example can be interpreted as private provision of public goods, where each player divides endowment between private consumption and public good contribution . Suppose that the total endowment is , so that the total quantity of public good is . The payoff is a multiplicative function of both private consumption and public good, for example . The marginal benefit function can be non-linear.

Example 3 (Oligopoly with a Non-linear Demand Function).

Suppose that oligopolists have identical constant marginal costs and produce identical good. Each oligopolist chooses a quantity (capacity) and the inverse demand function is for some and . The profit of firm is , where .

To compare different contests, I define informativeness as a partial order on all -player contests. Intuitively, a contest is equivalently defined by a partition of players. Each additional disclosure divides the players in one period into two groups. Therefore the new contest provides strictly more information to some players than the previous contest, whereas no player receives less information. Formally, I say that the contest is more informative than the contest , if the corresponding partition is finer than .

In particular, the simultaneous contest that does not provide any information about the efforts of other players is less informative than any other contest. In the other extreme, the sequential contest discloses efforts after each player and is therefore more informative than any other contest. Finally, the first-mover contest discloses information after the first player, whereas all other players make their moves simultaneously. The first-mover contest is less informative than any other single-leader contest .

3 Optimal Contests

3.1 Total Effort and Total Welfare

The most common objectives considered in the literature are minimizing or maximizing the total equilibrium effort . Hinnosaar (2018) showed that the total effort is strictly increasing in the informativeness of the contest, i.e. each additional disclosure increases the total equilibrium effort . Therefore the simultaneous contest minimizes and the sequential contest maximizes the total equilibrium effort. The intuition for this result comes from the discouragement effect. Efforts in contests are strategic substitutes. Therefore, with each additional public disclosure, each earlier-mover whose effort is now made visible to some additional later-movers has an additional incentive to increase the effort—it discourages these later-movers from exerting high effort. Moreover, in equilibrium this effect must be less than one-to-one, i.e. the decrease in efforts by later-movers is smaller than the increase in efforts by earlier-movers. Otherwise, a marginal increase in the effort of an earlier-mover would decrease the total effort and therefore increase ’s payoff. This would be a profitable deviation and thus violate equilibrium conditions.

Let us now look at total equilibrium welfare. For example, in the case of a normalized Tullock contest the total welfare is . This expression is decreasing in , so maximized by the simultaneous contest and minimized by the sequential contest. The intuition is simple—in a Tullock contest, the total prize is fixed. Additional players and additional disclosures lead to a higher total effort, which is costly and therefore welfare-reducing. The following proposition shows that these conclusions generalize to arbitrary payoffs and an arbitrary number of players.

Proposition 1 (Total Effort and Total Welfare).

The total equilibrium effort is minimized by the simultaneous contest and maximized by the sequential contest. The total equilibrium welfare is minimized by the sequential contest and maximized by the simultaneous contest.

3.2 Lowest Effort and Lowest Payoff

We need to first determine who is the player choosing the lowest effort in equilibrium and who gets the lowest payoff. The answer comes from the earlier-mover advantage—equilibrium efforts and payoffs of earlier-movers who are observed by more players are higher than the corresponding efforts and payoffs of later-movers.666See appendix A for a formal discussion. Therefore player chooses the lowest effort and gets the lowest payoff with any -player contest . The reason for this result is again the discouragement effect—earlier players choose higher efforts to discourage later players from exerting effort whenever their efforts are made public. By doing so, earlier players ensure higher and later players get lower payoffs.

The following proposition shows that both the lowest effort and the lowest payoff are minimized and maximized by the same contests as the total welfare—sequential and simultaneous contests respectively. The intuition is simple. As discussed above, each additional disclosure leads to higher efforts by earlier-movers and lower efforts by later-movers. Therefore the discouragement effect to the last player is increased with each disclosure. Moreover, additional disclosures lead to higher total equilibrium effort , which reduces the payoff of the last player even further.

Proposition 2 (Lowest Effort and Lowest Payoff).

Lowest equilibrium effort and lowest equilibrium payoff are minimized by the sequential contest and maximized by the simultaneous contest.

3.3 Highest Effort and Highest Payoff

The earlier-mover advantage result shows that the player who exerts the highest effort and gets the highest payoff is the first player. It is easy to see that the effort of player is minimized by the simultaneous contest. This is the contest which minimizes the total effort and where all efforts are equal. In all other contests, the total effort is higher and the effort of player is higher than the average, due to the discouragement effect, which means higher than in the simultaneous contest. Indeed, this is what figure (a)a confirms—for each , the highest equilibrium effort is minimized by the simultaneous contest.

Maximization of the highest effort is the first objective, where the optimal solution is not always one of the extremes, i.e. simultaneous or sequential contest. For example, let us consider three-player Tullock contests with a single leader.777In numerical examples, I normalize the prize and marginal cost to , so that the payoff of player is . For figures, I consider possible contests with to players. I use the Matlab code available at toomas.hinnosaar.net/contests/. There are two such contests. The first-mover contest has a total equilibrium effort and the highest effort . Adding a disclosure after player makes the contest sequential, i.e. . As argued above, this raises the total effort to . This reduces the marginal benefit of effort for all players. However, it also makes the discouragement effect of player stronger through indirect influence. Note that players and already observed the effort of player , so the direct discouragement effect is unchanged. However, in the sequential contest player observes player , who is influenced by player . In the case of Tullock contest payoffs the first effect dominates and the leader’s equilibrium effort reduces to . Numerical calculations summarized by figure (a)a show that the contest that maximizes the highest equilibrium effort in a Tullock contest with players is always one with a single leader and followers that are arranged pairwise, i.e.  when

is odd or

when is even.888The location of the second single-player period does not affect . Arranging the followers pairwise leads to a strictly higher effort by the first player than in any other contest, including the sequential contest.

(a) Highest effort. Green dash-dotted line indicates the single-leader contest with pairwise followers. The slightly lower red dash-dotted line indicates the first-mover contest.
(b) Highest payoff. Green dash-dotted line indicates contests and red long-dashed line indicates contests .
Figure 1: Highest effort and highest payoff in all normalized Tullock contests with players. The solid black line indicates sequential contests and dashed blue line simultaneous contests.

The observation that there should be a single first-mover is general and intuitive. Making first-movers’ effort observable to all players increases total effort only because of increased effort by the first player, so there is no trade-off. As discussed above, each additional disclosure has two opposite effects and the effect on highest effort depends on the weights to direct and indirect influences. For example, with exponential function the first-mover contest gives highest effort , whereas the sequential contest gives strictly larger highest effort . The literature on sequential oligopolies (starting from (Daughety, 1990)) has found that if the demand function is linear, then Stackelberg leaders behave as if there are no followers, i.e.  would be independent on the number and arrangement of followers. Hinnosaar (2019) provides the most general formulation of this Stackelberg independence result, but also shows that this result holds only when function is linear. Therefore the formal statement, in this case, provides only a qualitative result, showing that . Indeed, as any single-leader is optimal in the case of linear , the result cannot exclude any such contest from being optimal.

Finally, in the case when is large enough, we can say more regardless of the exact details of the payoff function. Namely, in this case, is close to its upper bound and therefore assuming that function is smooth, it can be closely approximated by a linear function. In particular, this means that the conclusion from linear demand extends here—any large single-leader contest leads to the highest effort that is arbitrarily close to the maximized highest effort. Figure (a)a also illustrates that while all single-leader contests are optimal in the limit, for the sequential contest the convergence is very fast, whereas for the first-mover contest the convergence is much slower.999The same arguments can be used to find the contest that minimizes or maximizes the -th highest effort or payoff when is linear or is large enough. Appendix D provides these results.

Proposition 3 (Highest Effort).

The highest effort is minimized by simultaneous contest. If contest maximizes the highest effort then . If is linear or is large enough, then any single-leader contest ensures highest effort that is arbitrarily close to maximum.

Maximizing highest equilibrium payoff balances a similar trade-off, but the downward force through reduced marginal benefit is more pronounced. Not only does it push effort down, but it also reduces , which directly reduces all payoffs. This means that we would naturally expect the optimal contest to have fewer disclosures than the contest that maximizes the highest equilibrium effort. Indeed, figure (b)b shows that among all Tullock contests with up to players, the first-mover contest is always optimal.

The proposition below formalizes this qualitative property—a contest that maximizes the highest equilibrium effort must have a single leader and has to be (weakly) less informative than a contest that maximizes the highest payoff. For example, in the case of linear function, one maximizer of the highest effort is the first-mover contest . As all other contests with a single leader are more informative, the immediate conclusion is that the first-mover contest is the unique maximizer of the highest payoff. In the case of linear function or a large number of players, we can therefore uniquely determine the optimal contest. It is always , which confirms the finding from figure (b)b.

Minimizing the highest payoff requires balancing a different trade-off. As we saw above, additional disclosures lead to larger highest effort due to a stronger discouragement effect. This would imply that minimizing the highest payoff requires a relatively uninformative contest. On the other hand, additional disclosures lead to a higher total effort, which reduces all payoffs. Let us compare for example three-player Tullock contests and . Contest gives total effort , highest effort and therefore highest payoff . Contest gives total effort , but highest effort , which is much larger than and therefore highest payoff . Figure (b)b shows that in the case of a Tullock contest with up to players, contest minimizes the highest payoff.

The formal result below provides only one general qualitative property for the contest that minimizes the highest payoff: the number of players in the first period must be weakly higher than in any other period, i.e.  for all . If this would not be the case, the designer could rearrange the groups while keeping the total effort unchanged and decreasing the highest effort, which would reduce the highest payoff.101010This comes from the independence of permutations result from Hinnosaar (2018), which shows that total equilibrium effort is independent of permutations of vector . Why can’t we say more? Other possible manipulations of the contests, such as moving a player from period 1 to period 2 or splitting up the period by an additional disclosure, lead to two opposite effects: on one hand they increase the total effort in the contest, which reduces all efforts as well as the payoffs directly, but on the other hand they increase the influence that the first player has through the discouragement effect. The relative magnitudes of these effects depend on the shape of the function .

In the case of linear or large contests, the optimal contest is again uniquely determined: it is always .111111Remark: when is very large, and therefore for all , which means that technically all contests are approximately optimal. However, as figure (b)b illustrates, in some contests this convergence is much faster than in others. By optimality I mean here the contest for which the value of the objective is maximized for large but finite values of . This confirms the finding from figure (b)b.

Proposition 4 (Highest Payoff).

If contest minimizes the highest equilibrium payoff , then for all . If is linear or is large enough, then the optimal contest is .

If contest maximizes the highest equilibrium payoff, then and is not more informative than any maximizer of the highest effort. If is linear or is large enough, then the optimal contest is .

3.4 Effort Inequality and Payoff Inequality

In this final part I study equilibrium effort inequality, defined as , and equilibrium payoff inequality, defined as . By the earlier-mover advantage result discussed above, these expressions are equivalent to and respectively. It is easy to see that both expressions are minimized by the simultaneous contest since this is the only contest where efforts and payoffs are equal for all players.

Maximization of effort inequality and payoff inequality leads to additional trade-offs. Consider the effort inequality first. As seen above, minimizing the lowest effort requires an informative contest. On the other hand, maximizing highest effort may involve pooling some of the later-movers. Therefore the effort inequality is maximized by a contest that is (weakly) more informative than the contest that maximizes the highest effort. Indeed, as figure (a)a shows, in Tullock contests with up to players the first effect dominates and the optimal contest is sequential. Let us compare again Tullock contests and . The first contest leads to maximized highest effort , but also relatively high lowest effort . The sequential contest leads to slightly lower highest effort , but the impact to the lowest effort is bigger, . Therefore the sequential contest maximizes the effort inequality.

The formal proposition proves these qualitative properties. It shows that the payoff-inequality-maximizing contest must have a single leader and it cannot be less informative than any contest that maximizes the highest effort. In the case when is linear or is large, the most informative maximizer of the highest effort is the sequential contest. Therefore, we can immediately conclude that the sequential contest must also be the unique maximizer of the equilibrium effort inequality, which confirms the result from figure (a)a.

(a) Effort inequality
(b) Payoff inequality. Green dot-dashed line indicates the first-mover contest.
Figure 2: Effort inequality and payoff inequality in all normalized Tullock contests with players. The solid black line indicates sequential contests and simultaneous contests lie on the horizontal axis.

Finally, maximizing payoff inequality has an additional first-order effect: disclosures increase and thus reduce all payoffs. This effect mechanically reduces payoff inequality as . In the three-player examples above, . However, . Therefore this additional effect is larger and is the three-player contest that maximizes payoff inequality. Figure (b)b shows that in the case of Tullock contests, this effect is strong enough so that for all , the contest that maximizes payoff inequality is always the first-mover contest .

The proposition below shows that the contest that maximizes payoff inequality must have a single leader. It is more informative than any maximizer of the highest payoff and less informative than any maximizer of the effort inequality. When function is linear or the contest is large, these conditions, unfortunately, are not very informative. All single-leader contests are more informative than the highest payoff maximizer and all contests are less informative than the effort inequality maximizer, which is the sequential contest. The proposition shows that we can in this case nevertheless uniquely determine that the optimal contest is the first-mover contest .121212Again, subject to a remark: when becomes large then all payoffs converge to zero and therefore any contest approximately maximizes the payoff inequality. However as figure (b)b clearly illustrates, in the first-mover contest converges to zero much faster than other contests. The optimal contest here means that it maximizes the payoff inequality with finite but arbitrarily large .

Proposition 5 (Effort Inequality and Payoff Inequality).

Both the equilibrium effort inequality and the equilibrium payoff inequality are minimized by the simultaneous contest.

If contest maximizes the equilibrium effort inequality, then and is not less informative than any maximizer of the highest effort. If is linear or is large enough, then is the sequential contest.

Any contest that maximizes the equilibrium payoff inequality must satisfy . Moreover, it cannot be less informative than any maximizer of the highest payoff and it cannot be more informative than any maximizer of the effort inequality. If is linear or is large enough, then is the first-mover contest.

4 Conclusions

In this paper, I studied contest architecture with public disclosures. Additional disclosures induce the discouragement effect that leads to higher efforts by earlier-movers, lower efforts by later-movers, and higher total effort. These effects have different implications to different objectives a contest designer may have. The optimal contests are summarized by table 1. Perhaps the most surprising finding of the paper is that for most objectives the optimal contest is one of the three standard contests the previous literature has been focused on—the simultaneous contest, the sequential contest, or the first-mover contest.

Objective function Minimizer Maximizer
Total effort Simultaneous Sequential
Total welfare Sequential Simultaneous
Lowest effort
Lowest payoff
Highest effort Simultaneous Single-leader
Highest payoff First-mover
Effort inequality Simultaneous Sequential
Payoff inequality First-mover
Table 1: Summary of the optimal contests for the objectives discussed in the paper. Contests marked with are optimal at least for (1) Tullock contests with , (2) contests with linear function for any , and (3) large contests. The simultaneous contest is , the sequential contest is , the first-mover contest is , and single-leader contest are for all (including the sequential and the first-mover contests).

References

  • Acemoglu and Jensen (2013) Acemoglu, D. and M. K. Jensen (2013): “Aggregate comparative statics,” Games and Economic Behavior, 81, 27–49.
  • Bergemann and Morris (2019) Bergemann, D. and S. Morris (2019): “Information Design: A Unified Perspective,” Journal of Economic Literature, 57, 44–95.
  • Bimpikis et al. (2019) Bimpikis, K., S. Ehsani, and M. Mostagir (2019): “Designing Dynamic Contests,” Operations Research, 67, 339–356.
  • Che and Gale (2003) Che, Y.-K. and I. Gale (2003): “Optimal Design of Research Contests,” American Economic Review, 93, 646–671.
  • Cournot (1838) Cournot, A.-A. (1838): Recherches sur les principes mathématiques de la théorie des richesses par Augustin Cournot, Chez L. Hachette.
  • Daughety (1990) Daughety, A. F. (1990): “Beneficial Concentration,” American Economic Review, 80, 1231–1237.
  • Dixit (1987) Dixit, A. (1987): “Strategic Behavior in Contests,” American Economic Review, 77, 891–898.
  • Doval and Ely (2019) Doval, L. and J. Ely (2019): “Sequential information design,” manuscript.
  • Ely and Szydlowski (2019) Ely, J. C. and M. Szydlowski (2019): “Moving the Goalposts,” Journal of Political Economy, forthcoming.
  • Gallice and Monzón (2019) Gallice, A. and I. Monzón (2019): “Co-operation in Social Dilemmas Through Position Uncertainty,” The Economic Journal.
  • Glazer and Hassin (1988) Glazer, A. and R. Hassin (1988): “Optimal contests,” Economic Inquiry, 26, 133–143.
  • Glazer and Hassin (2000) ——— (2000): “Sequential Rent Seeking,” Public Choice, 102, 219–228.
  • Hinnosaar (2018) Hinnosaar, T. (2018): “Optimal Sequential Contests,” manuscript.
  • Hinnosaar (2019) ——— (2019): “Stackelberg Independence,” manuscript.
  • Jensen (2010) Jensen, M. K. (2010): “Aggregative games and best-reply potentials,” Economic Theory, 43, 45–66.
  • Kahana and Klunover (2018) Kahana, N. and D. Klunover (2018): “Sequential lottery contests with multiple participants,” Economics Letters, 163, 126–129.
  • Kamenica and Gentzkow (2011) Kamenica, E. and M. Gentzkow (2011): “Bayesian Persuasion,” American Economic Review, 101, 2590–2615.
  • Konrad (2009) Konrad, K. A. (2009): Strategy and Dynamics in Contests, London School of Economics Perspectives in Economic Analysis, Oxford University Press, 1 ed., published: Paperback.
  • Martimort and Stole (2012) Martimort, D. and L. Stole (2012): “Representing equilibrium aggregates in aggregate games with applications to common agency,” Games and Economic Behavior, 76, 753–772.
  • Moldovanu and Sela (2001) Moldovanu, B. and A. Sela (2001): “The Optimal Allocation of Prizes in Contests,” American Economic Review, 91, 542–558.
  • Moldovanu and Sela (2006) ——— (2006): “Contest architecture,” Journal of Economic Theory, 126, 70–96.
  • Olszewski and Siegel (2016) Olszewski, W. and R. Siegel (2016): “Large Contests,” Econometrica, 84, 835–854.
  • Robson (1990) Robson, A. J. (1990): “Stackelberg and Marshall,” American Economic Review, 80, 69–82.
  • Taylor (1995) Taylor, C. R. (1995): “Digging for Golden Carrots: An Analysis of Research Tournaments,” American Economic Review, 85, 872–890.
  • Tullock (1967) Tullock, G. (1967): “The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft,” Economic Inquiry, 5, 224–232.
  • Tullock (1974) ——— (1974): The social dilemma: The economics of war and revolution, University publications.
  • Vojnović (2015) Vojnović, M. (2015): Contest Theory: Incentive Mechanisms and Ranking Methods, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • von Stackelberg (1934) von Stackelberg, H. (1934): Marktform und gleichgewicht, J. springer.

Appendix A Notation, Assumptions, and Useful Results

In this appendix, I describe additional notation and formalize technical assumptions that are necessary for formal proofs. I then describe a few useful results from the literature.

a.1 Notation

Instead of working directly with the marginal benefit function it is more convenient to work with the following functions . Each of these function captures a particular curvature property of function and can be interpreted as a higher-order strategic substitutability term.

Definition 1 (Functions and ).

Let . With this, let us define recursively as and .

For example, in the case of linear , for all . In the case of normalized Tullock payoffs and so and . Therefore is a polynomial of degree .

For a contest let us define its measures of information. Intuitively, it is a vector of integers, that captures the number of direct and indirect observations of other players’ efforts. Let me describe the construction with an example of contest . Each player observes its own effort. This is captured by the first measure . The second measure is the number of direct observations of other players’ efforts, . The third measure captures observations of observations, i.e. influences through one connection. In particular, (for example, player influences player , who in turn influences player ). Therefore in the example.

Definition 2 (Measures of Information ).

For a given contest , its measures of information are defined as , where is the sum of products of all possible -combinations of the set .

For each period , let denote the subcontest starting after period , i.e. . Then are denoted analogously to the original contest. For example, if , then and , therefore and .

Finally, let me define functions as follows131313Note that when , then is the whole contest.

(1)

These functions take the role of inverted best-response functions that I discuss below. Intuitively, the inverse functions describe what is the total effort when after period the cumulative effort is and all players after period behave optimally.

a.2 Technical Assumptions

The first technical assumption is sufficient to guarantee that the best-response functions of players are well-behaved. This is a sufficient assumption to guarantee both the existence and uniqueness of the subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium for contest .

Assumption 1 (Inverted Best-Responses are Well-Behaved).

For all , the function defined by equation 1 has the following properties:

  1. has a root in .141414Function , therefore it has exactly one root, . Let be the highest such root.

  2. for all .

  3. for all .

Moreover, .

The second assumption states that the efforts are higher-order strategic substitutes near equilibrium. This assumption is stronger than the standard assumption of strategic substitutes, which requires that higher effort of an opponent reduces the incentive for a player to exert effort. Higher-order influences matter in sequential games, where the earlier-mover may not only influence a follower directly but indirectly through changing the behavior of some players between them.

Assumption 2 (Higher-Order Strategic Substitutes).

for all .

Hinnosaar (2018) shows that the two assumptions are satisfied for Tullock contests with at least three players as well as in many other situations with well-behaving marginal benefit functions.

a.3 Useful Results

The proofs rely on a few useful results from earlier works. The main tool for the analysis is the characterization theorem, which characterizes the unique equilibrium for any contests.

Theorem 1 (Characterization Theorem (Hinnosaar, 2018)).

Under creftype 1 the total equilibrium effort is the highest root of , where

(2)

The equilibrium effort of player in period is .

Informativeness and equilibria:

As Hinnosaar (2018) shows, this result has strong implications for equilibrium behavior. The total equilibrium effort increases with the informativeness of the contest. Therefore it is minimized by the simultaneous contest (the least informative contest) and maximized by the sequential contest (the most informative contest).

Independence of permutations:

permutations in do not change the total equilibrium effort . For example, the contest has exactly the same total effort as the contest because . Of course, individual efforts may be affected, as they also depend on subcontest. But note that permutations within the subcontest do not affect individual equilibrium effort either: in the examples here, and is a permutation. Therefore .

Earlier-mover advantage:

take two players, from period and from a later period . Then and . As explained in the text, this means that highest effort is always , lowest effort , highest payoff , and lowest playoff .

Large contests:

Moreover, Hinnosaar (2019) shows that in the limit when the number of players becomes large, the equilibrium behavior converges to specific functional form. Intuitively, as the number of players becomes large and the total equilibrium effort increases with the number of players, it is quite natural that the total equilibrium effort converges to its full dissipation limit . As the function is smooth, we can approximate it with a linear function near arbitrarily closely when the number of players is large. Therefore it is not surprising that the equilibrium behavior of individual players converges to equilibrium behavior of the same game but with linear function.

Theorem 2 (Competitive Limits (Hinnosaar, 2019)).

Fix a sequence and let us increase at a particular period , while keeping other elements of the sequence unchanged. Then and for each player arriving in period ,

(3)

I use this result as follows. Note that is not determined, as with different the contest designer may want to use different disclosures. I use equation 3 as an approximation for the equilibrium behavior, i.e. each player chooses

(4)

Note that this approximation also implies that

(5)

Since is a smooth function and , we can approximate linearly near , i.e.

(6)

Appendix B Proofs

b.1 Proof of Proposition 1 (Total Effort and Total Welfare)

Results for follow from theorem 1. The total welfare is , so

(7)

Note that by theorem 1, each , therefore this condition is always satisfied. Each disclosure increases and therefore decreases total welfare.

b.2 Proof of Proposition 2 (Lowest Effort and Lowest Payoff)

As argued in the text, and by theorem 1, . Since is strictly decreasing in , the lowest effort is minimized when is maximized, i.e. by sequential contest, and maximized when is minimized, i.e. by simultaneous contest. Similarly, , where both and are decreasing in , which leads to the same conclusion.

b.3 Proof of Proposition 3 (Highest Effort)

Let us first consider minimization of the highest equilibrium effort . Let be the total equilibrium effort from simultaneous -player contest . Then clearly the highest equilibrium effort . Now take any non-simultaneous contest. As this contest is strictly more informative than the simultaneous contest, . Moreover, by the earlier-mover advantage result, the highest effort is strictly larger than the average, which proves the claim, since

(8)

Suppose now that maximizes the highest effort, which by theorem 1 is

(9)

I first claim that for all . If this is not the case, we can take a permutation of , which leaves unchanged, but increases the information measures of the subcontest , therefore increasing the highest effort. Next, I claim that . Suppose that this is not the case, i.e.  But the previous observation, . Consider an alternative contest . Then . Since , we have

Therefore and . Therefore . This means that each . Moreover, clearly . Therefore , which means that was not the maximal highest effort.

Finally, when the is linear or when number of players is large, then by the arguments above, the highest effort is (approximately) . Clearly, this is maximized by setting , i.e. a disclosure right after the first player. All other disclosures have no impact when is linear and a negligible impact when is large enough.

b.4 Proof of Proposition 4 (Highest Payoff)

Let be a contest that minimizes the highest equilibrium payoff . I claim that for all . If this is not the case, then there exists a permutation of such that is increased and and thus is unchanged. This would violate the optimality of . When is large, then by the highest equilibrium payoff is approximately

(10)

Minimizing this objective is equivalent to maximizing . We can do it in two steps. First, fix and choose optimal subcontest, which therefore needs to maximize subject to constraint that . Splitting each onto and always increases the product as . Therefore the maximized product and so the maximization problem is

(11)

Treating as a continuous variable and differentiating the objective gives

(12)

The objective is decreasing in for all , so there are only two candidates for the maximizer: either or . Direct comparison gives

(13)

Therefore the optimal large contest is .

Let be a maximizer of the highest payoff . The same arguments as in the proof of proposition 3 show that must be equal to (first for all , otherwise can take a permutation, and then if , splitting it makes the contest less homogeneous and thus decreases , which increases total payoff while also increasing player ’s share in it). Now, let be a contest that maximizes the highest effort. Let the corresponding effort profile be . Then by definition and , which cannot be satisfied unless . Therefore cannot be more informative than .

The final claim follows from the arguments above. With linear or large , one contest that maximizes the highest effort is . As the highest payoff maximizer must have and cannot be more informative than , it must coincide with .

b.5 Proof of Proposition 5 (Effort Inequality and Payoff Inequality)

As argued in the text, the simultaneous contest is the only contest where the efforts and payoffs of all players are equal, so it is the unique minimizer of both the equilibrium effort inequality as well as the equilibrium payoff inequality .

By the same arguments as with the highest effort and with the highest payoff, we get that both with effort inequality and payoff inequality maximizers. Note that since is independent of permutations of the subcontest and is independent of permutations in the whole contest, both inequalities are independent of permutations in .

Suppose that is an effort inequality maximizer and let the corresponding equilibrium effort profile be . Take any highest effort maximizer and let the corresponding effort profile be . Then by construction, and , which implies that . As is decreasing in it implies , which means that cannot be less informative than . Finally, if is linear or is large, then any single-leader contest maximizes the highest effort. One such contest is the sequential contest, which is more informative than any other contest. Therefore it must be the unique maximizer of the effort inequality in these cases.

Now, let be the maximizer of the equilibrium payoff inequality. As argued above, . Take any maximizer of the highest payoff . Then and therefore , which implies that . This means that cannot be less informative than . Next, suppose that maximizes the effort inequality. Then , which implies or equivalently . Therefore cannot be more informative than .

When is linear or is large, the results above do not tell us much, since none of the single-leader contests is less informative than (the maximizer of the highest payoff) and no contest is more informative than the sequential contest (the maximizer of the effort inequality). Therefore we have to proceed with direct proof. The equilibrium payoff inequality is (approximately)

(14)

I already proved that for any payoffs, including linear. The remaining question is how to arrange the remaining players into subcontest